CHAPTER II

 

THE RELEVANCE OF AFRICAN ETHICS

TO CONTEMPORARY AFRICAN SOCIETY

 

JAMES K. KIGONGO

 

            As we grapple with issues of development, we need to place them in the appropriate historical and social context.  In the case of Africa, this context has been determined by the encounter of two cultural and ethical paradigms that many observers and critics are inherently contradictory.  The position of the paper is that whereas we may perceive a contradiction in the conceptualization of the paradigms, the social reality is that they do co-exist.  This contradiction and co-existence calls for a critical inquiry from which we can discern fundamental elements vital for development.

            First co-existence is stressed in the section, “The reality of a synthesis.” Second, “African” is seen as problematic in the process of change” to some the idea of African, let alone Africa as a single entity, is an illusion. Third, Human relationship in African ethics attempts to present the substance of African traditional ethics. Fourth, “The problematic of social and moral change,” discusses the social paradigm that emerged subsequent to the cultural encounter, which was both a destabilising social pluralism and an enriching experience. Finally, “The problematic of the old moral order,” speaks of the tendency to fail to appreciate the relevance of African traditional ethics for contemporary African society. 1

 

THE REALITY OF A SYNTHESIS

 

            We need to recognize first of all the meeting of the African ethical tradition and the European ethical tradition when we conceive ethics in the contemporary African context, for this meeting causes conflict in our ethical conception and empirical experience.  African colonial experience shook the traditional conceptual paradigms and institutions bringing into question the African cultural foundation.  Despite the conflict, there tends to be a synthesis between the two traditions.  Indeed, historically contemporary Africa in most of its social domains is to a large extent a combination of the European and African cultural dynamics. In fact, what is happening in the moral sphere of contemporary African society is a manifestation of the convergence of European ethics and traditional African ethics, and, subsequently, a synthesis between the two emerges. 

            From the African experience, however, one notices the problematic identity.  Whereas on the one hand, some people conceive and suggest a heightened awareness and strong attachment to African cultural values (including the ethical values) that underlie Africa’s socio-cultural change, on the other hand, some incline towards alien values as more relevant to the modernization entailed in the change.  In the former position, there is a perception and concern for the relevance and continuity of African cultural values; hence a manifestation of the perception of continuity of African identity.  This position, however, does not deny the importance of European values.  While the African values are seen as more fundamental to the change, that is, as having primary importance, the European values are considered secondary. According to the second position, the African values are of secondary relevance to the new socio-cultural reality, for as modernity continues to gain a dominating impact on our life, there is a corresponding decline of the influence of the tradition and, therefore, a decline in its relevance to contemporary realities.

            It is in light of this dichotomous position that “the reality of a synthesis” is suggested.  This gives us a third position.2 The African and the alien are perceived as having equal importance in affecting the process of change because they are historical and contemporary realities.  That is to say, they are embedded in our history since the emergence of colonialism and thus significantly affect our contemporary perceptions.  We notice here a desire to be what we were originally yet, at the same time, a desire to embrace change, that is an identification with two contrasting realities.  We can notice a possibility here of deriving what is positive in the traditional African ethics and in the European ethics, thus a possibility of each enriching the other.  The aesthetic and moral richness of human relationships in the African culture would be some of the elements contributed by the traditional African ethics.  From European ethics, the emphasis of the autonomy and freedom of the individual, subsequently a person’s critical inclination, would be significant elements.

            Some would argue that you cannot have such a synthesis in reality, that it would be a mere mental abstraction in a situation of the cultural tendencies of one tradition to dominate the other.  The argument is drawn out of the colonial experience of Africa in which colonialism began a process of uprooting African culture from its “natural habitat,” and infusing its own. This put in question the African cultural foundation, manifesting what Serequeberhan aptly refers to as “the historical-political-existential crisis of an African saddled with a broken and ambiguous heritage.”3 My conception of synthesis here is the possibility of the cultural or ethical traditions enriching each other when they exist in a single social context.  In fact, when we have the strong attachment to what is traditional or African (hence African identity) despite, at the same time, the conspicuous existence of the alien, it seems that our perception of the dominating influence is rather more imagination than actually reality. Though colonialism strongly impinged on the African traditions and cultural consciousness and indeed shook the African cultural foundation, much of African cultural dynamism persisted.  Whereas the European cultural and intellectual colonization is a historical reality for Africa, it did not completely erode the sense of Africanity that was, in fact, the fundamental motivating factor of the independence struggle.  We may note here that the two traditions (African and European) do not only exist in a single social unity, but were fundamental opposites.  The sense of Africanity continues to have a strong impact on the African psyche and is bound to continue into the future through generational inheritance, though there is need for sensitization to it through education, both formal and informal, as explained towards the conclusion of this paper.   

            The synthesis is an enriching experience in the mind of the individual, enabling critical appreciation of the cultural and intellectual wealth of each of the two cultural traditions and an appreciation that we belong to both intellectual traditions. Nevertheless, what probably emerges clearly in view of the conflicting cultural and ethical traditions is a sense of doubt as to how we can proceed out of the apparent conflict, whether to give primary importance to what is African or to what is alien and how to merge the two.  While it may not be possible to resolve this skepticism, it could itself be a positive disposition because it could continue to sensitize us to the importance of both traditions. It is the sensitivity rather than the resolution that is more crucial, given that we cannot foresee with certainty the historical trends of the two traditions though we can be sure of their continued existence in the social context.

            In short, the main idea in this section is to draw our attention to the persistence of a strong ethical tradition inherited from the African traditional milieu. This exists together with the European ethical tradition, notwithstanding the colonial impingement.  The perceptual contradiction and the subsequent empirical experience though real, should not keep us from drawing on both strands to enrich our contemporary life and development.

 

THE CONCEPT OF ‘AFRICAN’ IN THE PROCESS OF CHANGE

 

            In view of the doubt noted in the previous section, the mention of “African society” tends to raise skepticism among some people, especially with regard to the concept of “African” in contemporary times.   The issue here is whether we can justifiably talk about “African society,” and hence “African culture” and “African ethics” in the context of contemporary changes.  The underlying idea is that as a result of the cultural change in Africa, especially during the last 100 years, Africanity is undergoing a process of erosion. An extreme position is that we cannot have a viable existence of the “African” given the overwhelming impact of alien elements, leading to what is perceived as a collapse of traditional culture and of traditional ethics.  The impact of globalization whose propelling cultural and economic elements are predominantly alien (especially European) and tend to be hegemonic enhances this skepticism. 

            The viability of the African, however, can be justified in the sense that we can still talk of a continuity of the African cultural content despite the change, though the essence and intensity of this content cannot be established with certainty.  In fact, African culture and ethics did not collapse.  Instead they lost their intrinsic importance in people’s thinking and assumed a peripheral role in the event of colonization and its attendant cultural impingement. Culture was viewed as the source which nourished all human activity in traditional society.  At the same time all human activity in the social context was viewed as having an ethical end, namely, that it would not only be good in itself but beneficial to the community as a whole, in the sense of enhancing the community’s well-being, such as cohesion and prosperity.  Today, as we realize the gaps of modernization, especially its de-emphasis of the traditional (in fact, traditional and modernity are perceived as contradictory terms, and culture as inimical to modernization), we revisit the past in order to develop new conceptual paradigms and find for modernization a strong ethical content. Hence, the contemporary critical investigation of values and culture, a kind of cultural renaissance, is a question for cultural and ethical renewal.4 

            The contemporary debate is a recognition not only of the persistence and relevance of traditional thought and values to the contemporary milieu, but also of the importance of a critical study and evaluation of the concepts and values. There are central to traditional thought as they underlie human culture and play a significant role in influencing change and thought in contemporary African society.  The influence, nevertheless, quite often tends to be subtle and not easily noticeable.  Indeed, such concepts and values constitute the background to the whole spectrum of human experience, not only the African. This renaissance, however, is not only an academic appreciation.  One notices also a call for a cultural renewal in the general society, which reflects an apparent doubt regarding the capacity of modernization without a culture enhancing human well-being.  It is, indeed, this society’s perception of the continuity and relevance of culture that nourishes the scholars’ perception of the persistence and relevance of traditional thought in the contemporary milieu, placing particular interest on ethical concerns.

            We may call this continuity the traditional identity.5   The empirical aspect of human social relations in the traditional African society has an abstract or conceptual form that underlies it and gives meaning and sense to the relations. This mental or spiritual heritage in which the community is rooted, Evandro Agazzi refers to as an implicit ethics.6  It is implicit because it is not expressed and formulated in definitive form.  But it has considerable influence on the people who belong to the culture, guiding and giving sense to the human social relations. As people undergo change in the different aspects of their life certain basic conceptions which persist and these constitute their heritage.7  It is in this sense that we can talk of an African ethical heritage in contemporary times.  However, when we try to understand this ethical heritage, it is important to distinguish it from custom, especially given the tendency to view African ethics and African custom as synonymous.  Whereas custom may be defined as the cultural norms of the society, ethics is the human social relations to which the cultural norms make a contribution.  The idea of “ethics in traditional Africa society” may be obvious, the same clarity may not obtain with regard to “ethics in the contemporary African society.”

            Some, however, would object to the idea of African ethics in a generalized sense, referring to Africa as a single entity encompassing the whole ethnic range of the traditional African society.  Wiredu, Gyekye and others have written extensively about the reality of common features across the ethnic diversity and, in the perspective of ethics, stressed the sense of communalism and its pervasiveness in each of the ethnic entities and in the different aspects of the African society such as religion, art, and music.  But K. A. Appiah, P. Hountondji, and D.A. Masolo would deny this unity and its implied conceptual commonality.8  The denial of universals or commonalities across the ethnic diversity is a relativistic view of human society

            Probably they would deny the notion of “African religion” in the singular sense rather than African religions, African art, etc., and by implication the notion of (traditional) “African society.”  In fact, Masolo suggests that “this generalization of an African identity, like most universals, is not real because it does not reflect the social experience of single subjects.”9  I assume that by subjects he refers to individual human beings. If used of individual ethnic groups, the generalization would not reflect the social experience of such groups.

            Of course, the individual human beings in the traditional society may not have significantly appreciated their belonging to a larger entity, beyond the ethnic.  But we cannot rule out any appreciation of it at all.  To them the ethnic was more primary than the larger one because it was closer in the person’s social milieu and level of mental abstraction.  The universal is more a conceptualisation of the philosopher(s) than of the individual in traditional society.  But this is in line with the professional philosopher’s task of conceptualization and abstraction of objective entities, notwithstanding the subjective awareness of the members of society, and in our case of traditional African society?

            On the whole, if we accept the persistence of the traditional ethical strand in the contemporary milieu, the concept of what is African becomes real rather than an illusion.  We continue to cherish African identity, which cannot be given another cultural tag. Whereas we can talk of the ethics of a specific ethnic group in Africa, there are different ethnic groups in Africa that are described as African, for they share commonalities (among then ethical) that gives them the collective identity of African.

 

HUMAN RELATIONSHIP IN AFRICAN ETHICS

 

            A fundamental unity between the different human beings in the community, i.e., a unity of human relationship, underlies traditional African ethics.  African ethics places considerable value on conformity of the individual to the social group in order to preserve the unity of human relationship.  It could be said that in a way African thought is, indeed, more concerned with the relationship than with the different entities which constitute the relationship.  All human behaviour is expected to conform to this value to ensure social harmony.  Human relationship and social harmony are vital elements in the African sense of moral aesthetics.10

            According to John S. Mbiti, it is only in terms of other people that the individual himself is conscious of his own being, his own duties, his privileges and responsibilities towards himself and towards other people: “I am because we are, and since we are, therefore I am.”11  This is “a morality of `conduct’ rather than a morality of ‘being,’”12 or of personal morality.  It is a morality of conduct in the sense that it is one’s relationships and, therefore, conduct in the social sphere that dictates one’s sense of morality. This morality occurs in contrast to emphasizing an individual’s sense of self, autonomy or being, that is, of the self which does not place much value on the social relationships.  The former was a strong awareness of one’s existence and relationship with others in the community, a strong sense of “social self.” The support of others was more important than one’s capacities to achieve one’s existential ends—hence the value of corporate existence. 

            Corporate existence signified a responsibility of many for one. First, the others had to look after the well-being of the individual, i.e., the responsibility of many for one. Second, the individual had to look after the well-being of others.  The latter was motivated by the former.  Here we note a collaborative relationship between the individual and society that helped to build and sustain a moral character in a person and moral order (social harmony) in the society.  These two elements helped build a strong sense of belonging and identity in the society. 

            However, the fact that African ethics emphasizes human relationship shows the significance attached to the individual human being.  The human being is perceived as the centre of the relationship, and as an active agent and participant in the relationship. The emphasis is not on the autonomy, freedom, and critical inclination of the individual in the sense of Socratic ethics, but on an appreciation of the status and role of the individual in the ethical and socio-economic pattern, which entails the individuals’ active agency and participation.  One could thus say that whereas European ethics conceives the individual as an intellectual being, emphasizing the faculty of reason as the basic tenet in moral conduct, African ethics conceives the individual as an ethical entity.  It is, indeed, this ethical perception that makes the relationship human.  Quite often, however, Africans fail to appreciate the ethical individuality of the human being in African ethics because most of the authors have concentrated on the element of African communalism and given an impression that the human individuality is swallowed up by the sense of communalism and not so predominant.13 Mbiti probably is the most outstanding culprit here.  Some perceive an authoritarian strand built in the communalistic culture almost as the sole determinant of African ethics. 

            The perception of the authoritarian strand is drawn from the education system in the traditional society that emphasized socialization of the individual into the established knowledge already created by former generations.14 Much of this knowledge was custom, which carried with it a very strong communal content.  Moreover, as Njoroge and Bennaars observe, education was socially controlled and in its different forms was consciously and deliberately practiced to cultivate ethical values.15 Thus, a tendency emerges to view traditional ethics and custom as synonymous. Thus, the authoritarian strand is perceived because of the conventional and authoritarian nature of custom, which is supposed to be respected and obeyed uncritically or without question.  It arises also out of African ethics placing considerable value on the conformity of the individual to the social group which sinks deep into the African social consciousness.

            Briefly, while the sense of relationship and community underlies African traditional ethics, in contrast to the European sense of autonomy, the individual is not perceived as just a mere presence in the community. As an individual, he is perceived both as the centre of the relationship and also as contributing to its sustenance. Hence, he possesses an ethical status and contributes a role in the ethical and entire social spectrum.

 

THE PROBLEMATIC OF SOCIAL AND MORAL CHANGE

 

            The intrusion of external culture in Africa was such that it did not allow a reciprocation between the two cultures so that both would benefit from each other.  Instead, Europe began a process of uprooting the African culture from its “natural habitat,” and infusing its own culture, hence, beginning a problematic social change. The process was problematic in the sense that it favoured the colonizer and set a trend towards marginalization of what was African, both by the colonizer and the colonized.  Hence, the re is now a skepticism about the viability of what is African exists.  The change also involves an increasing tendency towards social pluralism in the ethnic, cultural, religious, political, and economic areas of the society. 

            With this dual social orientation, morality in the African society is changing from inclination to the collective good—the communalistic characteristic of traditional society—to personal morality. This, however, tends to be perverted, rather than to be based on personal autonomy and inner conviction. From this follows a perversion of the sense of moral value, leading to its increasing deficiency. Whereas any all societies normally are characterized by some degree of limitation in morality, the perverted personal morality has been so fundamental a factor in African society’s historical evolution, that it has caused a cultural disruption in moral perception, and hence a problematic moral change.  This became the source of the perceptual instability manifested in the conflict of the African ethical tradition and the European ethical tradition.

            We may speak of a moral consensus in the ethnic community as part of the community’s cultural evolution.  Such evolution was not ensured in the new heterogeneous national society that emerged out of a revolutionary change.  The radical departure did not enable the people to grasp and adopt the new social milieu with its new moral orientation and its moral implications.  There was a fundamental moral challenge in synthesizing the two conflicting moral tendencies of individuality and the collective good, let alone the need to identify oneself with the common good as entailed by the diversity.  As a consequence, appropriate moral values could not evolve.  Such deficiency in moral development entailed a potential for the development of individualism.16 

            In the contemporary society, the increasing consciousness of personal freedom and personal interests, coupled with the increasing social pluralism and increasing diversity of individually-oriented interests, without a corresponding increase in appreciation of social obligation, makes the fundamental moral challenge still more problematic. The individuality of the person and the diversity of interests in themselves do not hinder the development of a moral unity of individual interests within the universalizable common good. Rather, it is the failure of the mental orientation of the individual to appreciate the moral question and its ramifications. The sense of self and personal interests (the negative sense of individuality) tends to override the sense of a social being to pursue one’s interests while at the same time being attentive to the interests of the others—those interests that are universal.

            With the tendency towards individualism, a person’s sense of moral value tends to incline more to what benefits him, his family or his ethnic group, which entails a narrow or restricted sense of moral value.  In the family and ethnic group, one anticipates some immediate gain because these are closer to him in his social perspective and relationships. One perceives in them a sense of identity and belonging.  Within the context of the nation and the contemporary urbanized society generally, which is increasingly becoming pluralistic and materialistic, a sense of identity and belonging is present but not adequate. The materialistic inclination that makes our conception of value more utilitarian, thus undermining the conception of moral value, manifests itself in the increasing practice of corruption and generally in the pursuit of life in the society as an economic activity. Primarily, economics is pursued without due regard to the rights and interests of other persons, except where they add to one’s economic advantages.  We see an increasing trend towards materialization and commercialization of human and social life, though at the same time this is provoking great ethical concern and, in many instances, a public call to return to traditional ethics. This legitimises the relevance of African ethics to contemporary African society.

            In short, the new social and moral context of Africa consequent to the intrusion of external culture not only began the alienation of African from the traditional ethical orientation but also caused a social pluralism.  Because external coercion motivated the two trends, they did not enable an internal dynamism in the African society to evolve an appropriate ethical consciousness.  The personal morality that was the dominant strand in the external culture—and to large extent in its perverted individualistic form—became the dominant moral trend, hence perpetuating the perversion of the African ethical sense.

 

THE PROBLEMATIC OF THE OLD MORAL ORDER

 

            With regard to the question of identifying with the common good, though we see continuity in the sense of humanity and its derivative sense of corporate existence, both deriving their roots from traditional morality, society tends to fail to appreciate the meaning and relevance of the “old moral order” for the new and complex moral order.  Thus, many people take the new moral milieu for granted.  This uncritical response to the contemporary moral predicament for some points to the “collapse” of the traditional ethics.

            Such intellectual inability to grasp the meaning of the old moral order and its relevance in the contemporary moral situation means that we are not only unable to comprehend the fundamental nature of this order, but also to comprehend a fundamental solution to the moral conflict.  One fundamental practical consequence of the moral deficiency, besides the intellectual inability to grasp its nature, let alone its solution, is the increasing polarization between individualism and the common good.  This dichotomization is compounded by the lack of a conscious institutionalized effort by the society to grasp the problem and seek a solution.

            However, whereas the problem of ethics has not received a serious critical discussion by African scholars, the relevance of African ethics to contemporary African society has manifested itself in the theorization by African scholars of the relevant political and economic theory for contemporary development. In particular, they theorize on what the nature of the African state should be and the course of the socio-economic development Africa ought to pursue.

            The relevance of African ethics in this theorization can be discerned in terms of the theme of the African sense of communalism. Contemporary African scholars have, indeed, reminded us that this communalism was not only a matter of social cooperation, but also of the inherent relationship of all human beings in the society, besides a perception of the centrality of the individual person in this relationship and its socio-economic configuration.  Interpreting communalism in the present context, they have conceived the nation-state as a moral community where human relationships and the good of the individual are viewed as more important in motivating development than material considerations.  This humanistic consideration thus became the central idea in African socialism.  Where academicians such as Wiredu and Gyekye recognize the continued existence of this sense of humanism in the contemporary African society in their numerous discourses on the African society, political leaders like Kwame Nkrumah, Julius Nyerere, Kenneth Kaunda, and Leopold Sedar Senghor have placed considerable significance on it in their socio-political theories.

            Nevertheless, some like Ruch and Anyanwu have argued that Nkrumah contradicted himself in his advocacy of African communalism in his philosophical consciencism when he places so much emphasis on the material aspect of development.17 This is exactly the source of the ethical dilemma in Africa today, that is, the failure to perceive the possibility of the co-existence of the material and the moral with the former strongly motivated by the sense of individualism inherent in European ethics. They are always perceived as contradictory, opposed to each other, with no mutuality between them.  It is in view of this possibility that I propose the possibility of a synthesis between the African and European ethical traditions.

            Thus, we have the African ethical heritage persisting to the present, but its meaning, let alone coexistence with and contribution to the materially motivated sense of development, cannot be sufficiently appreciated and some are skeptical about a synthesis.  This presents a fundamental challenge to contemporary African society and particularly to education.  Whereas the critical investigation of values and culture noted in the first section of this paper would contribute to sensitizing the African intelligentia to the appreciation of the synthesis, a broader approach would be required to sensitize this society in this regard.  Curriculum development in the entire education system needs to be more conscious of the problematic of the old moral order and give more attention to the paradigms of the ethical dilemma.  The consciousness of the relevance of African cultural and ethical heritage to the contemporary society needs strong development in the educational system.  At the same time, education needs to evolve a concept of development that is not biased in favor of material orientation or motivated by the sense of individualism. Education must synthesize the individual and human relationships.  The “third way” can most effectively be presented by a conscious and deliberate orientation of education.  African scholars would be needed to guide this orientation, but can do so only after they have given focused and sufficient critical attention to the problem of ethics.

            However, the presence of the African and European ethical tradition would not in itself be an absolute condition for realizing synthesis, which would enhance society’s well-being.  Whereas the material orientation and sense of individuality when perverted hinder the realization of the sense of community, the communalistic character of the traditional society and its attendant social obligation impinges on the sense of individuality and the motivation for self-realization.  Thus, another fundamental challenge is posed to education, namely, to guide the individuals between what would be positive and rational, on one hand, and negative and irrational, on the other, to an appropriate synthesis fostering the well-being of society.  But this could not be adequately discussed in this paper.

            On the whole, while Africans are conscious of the continuity of the African ethical tradition in contemporary society, the significance of this old moral order for contemporary society is not adequately appreciated. This lack creates an intellectual and moral vacuum in which individualism flourishes. The vacuum is manifest in our discourse and pursuit of development, endangering our inability to harmonize the material and the moral interests of development.  But if we did appreciate the need for this harmony, the best place to root out its underlying concepts and problematic would be the education system.

NOTES

 

[1] The subject of this paper was first presented by the author and discussed at seminars involving students and lecturers at the Universities of Witwatersrand, Durban-Westville, and Zululand in South Africa in April 2000.  The author is grateful to the Department of Philosophy at each of these universities for their invitation.

2 The author subscribes to this position.

3 Tsenay Serequeberhan in the “Introduction to his book African Philosophy: The Essential Readings (St. Paul, Minnesota, Paragon House, 1996), p.9.

            4 Whereas the European renaissance signifies ‘rebirth of knowledge’ and the African ‘a cultural renewal,’ an element of rebirth of knowledge can be discerned in the latter in the sense that the African perception of the intrinsic value of culture was an important epistemological aspect which the African renaissance wanted to restore, hence to this extent it was a rebirth of knowledge.  When this cultural renewal is viewed in the specific ethical sense, we see the concern for renewal focused on the African sense of community, which is basic to the traditional ethics.  This sense of community manifested itself in, and motivated, the different aspects of the traditional society such as economics and politics.  At the same time it was expressed in traditional religion, music, art, etc., and this is an underlying element of culture.

        5 ‘Traditional’ here refers to long-established elements that are indigenous, i.e., originate from within the culture, are integrated in the way of life of the people and are passed on to succeeding generations. Some of these elements persist and continue to change.

            6 Here I borrow Agazzi’s idea of an implicit philosophy, which underlies the way of life of all human communities, characterizes every culture, and gives it a typical character distinct from others. See Evandro Agazzi “Philosophies as Self-consciousness of Cultures,” in H. Odera Oruka and D.A. Masolo, Philosophy and Culture (Nairobi, Bookwise Ltd., 1983), pp.1-5.  The concept of African (traditional) ethics is not a body of knowledge in the sense of a moral philosophy, but an ethical orientation, or a morality. This is not to suggest that a body of knowledge on African ethics cannot be developed, for we can distinguish some conceptual knowledge related to ethics that used to guide human conduct and social relations.  In fact, the theory of European ethics was developed as an interpretation of certain ethical conceptions and practices in the European society.

7 Zubairi ‘b. Nasseem talks about the African heritage and its continuity and contribution in contemporary times, in “African Heritage and Contemporary Life:  An Experience of Epistemological Change”, in A.T. Dalfovo, The Foundations of Social Life: Ugandan Philosophical Studies 1 (Washington, D.C: The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy, 1992), pp. 17-36.

8 This can be inferred from their denial of African philosophy in the generalized sense of Africa as  a single entity.  See Chyme Anthony Appiah, In My Father’s House: Africa in the Philosophy of Culture  (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992), pp. 73-84; Paulin J. Hountondji, African Philosophy: Myth and Reality, Trans.  Henri Evans (London: Hutchinson University Library for Africa, 1983), pp. 60-62; and D.A. Masolo, “African Philosophy and the Postcolonial: Some Misleading Abstractions about Identity,” in Emmanuel Chukwudi Eze, Postcolonial African Philosophy: A Critical Reader (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Blackwell Publishers, 1997), p. 291.

9 Ibid., p.291.

10 In many societies this value tends to persist in time despite the impact of pluralistic and individualistic tendencies

11 John S. Mbiti, African Religions and Philosophy (Nairobi: East African Educational Publishers Ltd., 1969), pp.108-109.

12 Ibid., p. 214. Refer also to Gyekye Chyme, African Cultural Values: An Introduction (Philadelphia: Sankofa Publishing Company, 1996), pp.58-62.

13 Gyekye elaborates on this appreciation of the status and role of the individual in society, in African Cultural Values, p. 50, and in An Essay on African Philosophical Thought: The Akan Conceptual Scheme, rev. ed (London: Cambridge University Press, 1987), pp. 154-168.  We need to note that the emphasis on the intellectual and on the ethical by European and African ethics respectively does not mean that the other element is not important in the other ethical traditions.  Traditional African education recognized the individual’s intellectual individuality by its practice of imparting ideas (especially to the young) in the form of riddles and proverbs, because the learner was thought to have critical and rational capacity to interpret and appreciate the moral message involved and, thus, to choose the right course of action.  This method of education was an instrument for building moral character on the basis of independent thinking.  At the stage of adulthood there was the practice of reaching crucial decisions in the community by consensus after weighing various individual statements of the issue.

14 See R.J. Njoroge and G.A. Bennaars, Philosophy and Education in Africa (Nairobi: Transafrica Press, 1986), p. 145; D.A. Masolo, “Philosophy and Culture: A Critique,” in H. Odera-Oruka and D.A. Masolo, ibid., p.48; and Asavia Wandira, Indigenous Education in Uganda (Kampala: Department of Education Makerere University, 1972), p. 225

15 Ibid., p.145

16 We need here to establish a distinction between the notion of ‘individuality’ and ‘individualism.’  Individuality is an expression of one’s being and the source of one’s freedom, which certainly are two positive elements. In its practical manifestation, it is the pursuance of goals that are self-oriented, i.e., they have the individual as the centre of interest.  However, such self-centred or self-oriented goals can, and sometimes, do have a moral worth or value which can be a source of the common good which is universalizable.  If the fostering of my self-interests is negative, that is, harms the good of others or obstructs or is likely to obstruct its realization, then individuality becomes individualism.

            17 E.A. Ruch and K.C. Anyanwu, African Philosophy: An Introduction to the Main Philosophical Trends in Contemporary Africa (Rome: Catholic Book Agency, 1981), pp. 324-340.